Copyright | Copyright (C) 2023 Yoo Chung |
---|---|
License | GPL-3.0-or-later |
Maintainer | dev@chungyc.org |
Safe Haskell | Safe-Inferred |
Language | GHC2021 |
Part of Ninety-Nine Haskell Problems. Some solutions are in Solutions.P53.
Documentation
isTheorem :: [Formula] -> Formula -> Bool Source #
In propositional logic, if a formula \(X\) is always true when a set of axioms \(\mathrm{S}\) are true, then \(X\) is said to be valid given \(\mathrm{S}\).
The resolution rule is an inference rule in propositional logic where two clauses with complementary literals can be merged to produce another clause. Specifically, if clauses \(x \vee a_1 \vee \ldots \vee a_m\) and \(\neg x \vee b_1 \vee \ldots \vee b_n\) are true, then the clause \(a_1 \vee \ldots \vee a_m \vee b_1 \vee \ldots \vee b_n\) must also be true. This is commonly expressed as
\[ x \vee a_1 \vee \ldots \vee a_m \hspace{2em} \neg x \vee b_1 \vee \ldots \vee b_n \above 1pt a_1 \vee \ldots \vee a_m \vee b_1 \vee \ldots \vee b_n \]
The resolution rule can be used with conjunctive normal forms to prove whether or not a given formula \(X\) is valid given a set of axioms \(\mathrm{S}\). It is a proof by contradiction, and the procedure is as follows:
Conjunctively connect the formulas in \(\mathrm{S}\) and the negation of \(X\) into a single formula \(Y\).
For example, if the axioms are \(x\) and \(y\), and the given formula is \(z\), then \(Y\) would be \(x \wedge y \wedge \neg z\).
- Do not apply the resolution rule to the values of true and false. If \(Y\) contains raw true or false values, transform \(Y\) into a form which contains none.
- Convert \(Y\) into conjunctive normal form; see Problems.P52.
If there are two clauses for which the resolution rule can be applied, add the new clause to \(Y\) and repeat until an empty clause is inferred or if no new clauses can be added. Filter out tautologies, i.e., clauses which will always be true because it contains both a variable and its logical complement.
- If the empty clause has been inferred, then false has been inferred from \(Y\). I.e., there is a contradiction, so \(X\) must have been valid given the axioms \(\mathrm{S}\).
- If no more clauses can be inferred, then \(X\) cannot be inferred to be valid.
Given a list of axioms and a formula, use the resolution rule to determine whether the formula is valid given the axioms.
Examples
When \(x \wedge y \wedge z\) is true, then obviously \(x \vee y\) is true, so
>>>
:{
isTheorem [ Variable "X", Variable "Y", Variable "Z" ] $ Disjoin [ Variable "X", Variable "Y" ] :} True
When \(x \to y\) and \(y \to z\), or equivalently \(\neg x \vee y\) and \(\neg y \vee z\), then it is also the case that \(x \to z\), so
>>>
:{
isTheorem [ Disjoin [ Complement $ Variable "X", Variable "Y" ] , Disjoin [ Complement $ Variable "Y", Variable "Z" ] ] $ Disjoin [ Complement $ Variable "X", Variable "Z" ] :} True
Just because \(x\) is true does not mean that \(y\) is true, so
>>>
isTheorem [ Variable "X" ] $ Variable "Y"
False
If there is a contradiction, then everything is both true and false, so
>>>
isTheorem [ Variable "X", Complement $ Variable "X" ] $ Value False
True
Represents a boolean formula.
Value Bool | A constant value. |
Variable String | A variable with given name. |
Complement Formula | Logical complement. I.e., it is true only if its clause is false. |
Disjoin [Formula] | Disjunction. I.e., it is true if any of its clauses are true. |
Conjoin [Formula] | Conjunction. I.e., it is true only if all of its clauses are true. |